Economist: Government intervention in the free market in pursuit of socially desirable goals can affect supply and demand, thereby distorting prices. The ethics of such intervention is comparable to that of administering medicines. Most medicines have harmful as well as beneficial effects, so the use of a type of medicine is ethically justified only when its nonuse would be significantly more harmful than its use. Similarly, government intervention in the free market is justified only when it _______.

Summary

The author draws an analogy between the ethics of administering medicine and the ethics of government intervention. Since most medicines have both harmful and beneficial effects, using a medicine is justified only when not using it would cause a lot more harm than using it. Similarly, since government intervention in the free market for the purpose of social engineering can distort prices, such intervention is justified only when failure to intervene causes a lot more harm than the intervention.

Strongly Supported Conclusions

We’re looking to fill in the concerning what is required in order for government intervention in the free market to be justified. Based on the analogy to medicine, we can conclude that government intervention is justified only when the failure to intervene is a lot more harmful than intervention.

A
would likely be approved of by the majority of the affected participants

Unsupported. The analogy doesn’t condition the ethical use of medicine on approval, so it doesn’t make sense to complete the analogy with a comment on approval.

B
has been shown to have few if any significantly harmful effects

Unsupported. The analogy conditions the ethical use of medicine on a comparison between using medicine vs. not using the medicine. So it doesn’t make sense to complete the analogy with a comment that doesn’t involve a comparison between intervention and not having intervention.

C
is believed unlikely to significantly exacerbate any existing problems

Unsupported. The analogy conditions the ethical use of medicine on a comparison between using medicine vs. not using the medicine. So it doesn’t make sense to complete the analogy with a comment that doesn’t involve a comparison between intervention and not having intervention.

D
would do less damage than would result from the government’s not intervening

Strongly supported. Use of medicine is ethical only when not using it is more harmful than using it. Similarly, intervention is ethical only when not intervening is more harmful than intervening.

E
provides a solution to some otherwise insoluble problem

Unsupported. The analogy does not condition the ethical use of medicine on the provision of a solution. The requirement involve comparing the harm of using medicine vs. not using it. So it doesn’t make sense to complete the analogy with a comment on solutions.


4 comments

The proportion of fat calories in the diets of people who read the nutrition labels on food products is significantly lower than it is in the diets of people who do not read nutrition labels. This shows that reading these labels promotes healthful dietary behavior.

Summarize Argument: Phenomenon-Hypothesis
The author hypothesizes that reading nutrition labels causes healthier dietary behavior. This is based on a correlation. The proportion of fat calories in the diets of people who read nutrition labels is lower than it is in the diets of people who don’t read nutrition labels.

Identify and Describe Flaw
The author assumes that the correlation is explained by reading nutrition labels causing healthier dietary behavior. This overlooks alternate explanations. In particular, perhaps there’s a common cause that leads people to eat healthier and to read nutrition labels. Maybe the kind of person who’s into losing weight will read nutrition labels and be more careful about their diet.

A
illicitly infers a cause from a correlation
The author assumes a causal relationship based on the correlation between reading nutrition labels and having a lower proportion of fat in one’s diet.
B
relies on a sample that is unlikely to be representative of the group as a whole
The evidence isn’t a sample. We’re told about a statistic concerning people who read nutrition labels and people who don’t. There’s no indication that the statistic is based on just a part of the overall population.
C
confuses a condition that is necessary for a phenomenon to occur with a condition that is sufficient for that phenomenon to occur
The argument’s reasoning isn’t based on conditional logic, so there’s no confusion of sufficient and necessary conditions.
D
takes for granted that there are only two possible alternative explanations of a phenomenon
The author doesn’t assume “two” possible alternative explanations. The author assumes there’s only one — that reading nutrition labels causes healthier dietary behavior.
E
draws a conclusion about the intentions of a group of people based solely on data about the consequences of their behavior
The conclusion isn’t about intentions. It’s simply a causal claim about the effects of reading nutrition labels. The conclusion does not assert that people who read nutrition labels are doing so in order to improve their diets.

23 comments

Some paleontologists have suggested that Apatosaurus, a huge dinosaur, was able to gallop. This, however, is unlikely, because galloping would probably have broken Apatosaurus’s legs. Experiments with modern bones show how much strain they can withstand before breaking. By taking into account the diameter and density of Apatosaurus leg bones, it is possible to calculate that those bones could not have withstood the strains of galloping.

Summarize Argument: Counter-Position

Paleontologists who believe that Apatosaurus could gallop are probably wrong. Experiments with modern bones show that Apatosaurus’s leg bones could not have withstood the strains of galloping. These experiments show that galloping would probably have broken Apatosaurus’s legs. Therefore, it is unlikely that Apatosaurus galloped.

Identify Conclusion

The conclusion is the author’s opinion that some paleontologists are likely wrong in their belief that Apatosaurus could gallop.

A
Galloping would probably have broken the legs of Apatosaurus.

This is a sub-conclusion of the argument, not the main conclusion. The claim that galloping would likely have broken Apatosaurus’s legs supports the main conclusion that the paleontologists are probably incorrect in hypothesizing that Apatosaurus could gallop.

B
It is possible to calculate that Apatosaurus leg bones could not have withstood the strain of galloping.

This is an unstated premise—an assumption—that supports the argument’s sub-conclusion. Modern bone experiments only support the claim that Apatosaurus’s legs would have broken from galloping if it’s possible to calculate whether Apatosaurus’s leg bones could withstand the strain.

C
The claim of paleontologists that Apatosaurus was able to gallop is likely to be incorrect.

This correctly captures the stimulus’s main conclusion. The stimulus concludes that the claim made by some paleontologists that Apatosaurus could gallop is “unlikely,” or as (C) states, “likely to be incorrect.”

D
If galloping would have broken the legs of Apatosaurus, then Apatosaurus was probably unable to gallop.

This is an unstated premise supporting the main conclusion. The author concludes that Apatosaurus probably couldn’t gallop because galloping would likely have broken its legs. This conclusion assumes that Apatosaurus wouldn’t have galloped if doing so would have broken its legs.

E
Modern bones are quite similar in structure and physical properties to the bones of Apatosaurus.

This is an unstated premise, which supports the stimulus’s sub-conclusion that galloping would likely have broken Apatosaurus’s legs. The experiments with modern bones support this sub-conclusion because the stimulus assumes that modern bones are similar to those of Apatosaurus.


6 comments

A new process enables ordinary table salt to be fortified with iron. This advance could help reduce the high incidence of anemia in the world’s population due to a deficiency of iron in the diet. Salt is used as a preservative for food and a flavor enhancer all over the globe, and people consume salt in quantities that would provide iron in significant amounts.

Summarize Argument
The author concludes that fortifying salt with iron could help reduce the general incidence of anemia. People around the world consume enough salt that this advance would significantly increase their iron intake, thus remedying the iron deficiency that causes anemia.

Identify Argument Part
The referenced text supports the argument’s conclusion. Since people around the world eat enough salt for iron-fortified salt to make a health difference, iron-fortified salt could decrease the incidence of anemia brought on by iron deficiency.

A
It is the conclusion of the argument.
The author concludes that iron-fortified salt could help reduce the general instance of anemia. The reference text supports this conclusion.
B
It provides support for the conclusion of the argument.
The referenced text is a premise. It supports the conclusion by showing how salt is broadly-used and would therefore make a global difference.
C
It is a claim that the argument is directed against.
The referenced text supports the argument. Why would iron-fortified salt reduce anemia in the world’s population? Because people around the world use enough salt that the iron fortification would have an effect.
D
It qualifies the conclusion of the argument.
The conclusion is that iron-fortified salt would reduce the general incidence of anemia. The referenced text supports that claim rather than qualifying its scope.
E
It illustrates a principle that underlies the argument.
The referenced text isn’t a principle. It’s a fact used to support the conclusion about iron-fortified salt reducing anemia.

7 comments

Populations of a shrimp species at eleven different Indonesian coral reefs show substantial genetic differences from one reef to another. This is surprising because the area’s strong ocean currents probably carry baby shrimp between the different reefs, which would allow the populations to interbreed and become genetically indistinguishable.

"Surprising" Phenomenon
Why are shrimp at different coral reefs genetically distinct when ocean currents mix up baby shrimp between populations?

Objective
A hypothesis resolving this discrepancy must explain why the intermingling of baby shrimp between reefs is not enough to make those shrimp genetically indistinguishable. It will imply that baby shrimp exchanged between reefs do not breed with each other, or that their interbreeding is not enough to blur the genetic lines between populations.

A
The genetic differences between the shrimp populations are much less significant than those between shrimp and any other marine species.
This does not explain why the shrimp are genetically distinct. If the shrimp have similar genetics, their failure to interbreed is more surprising, not less.
B
The individual shrimp within a given population at any given Indonesian coral reef differ from one another genetically, even though there is widespread interbreeding within any such population.
This deepens the mystery. If the shrimp are capable of interbreeding despite significant genetic differences, then their failure to interbreed between reefs is more surprising.
C
Before breeding, shrimp of the species examined migrate back to the coral reef at which they were hatched.
This explains why the shrimp populations do not interbreed. Baby shrimp carried to other reefs do not breed until traveling back to their home reefs, so shrimp born at different reefs do not breed with each other.
D
Most shrimp hatched at a given Indonesian coral reef are no longer present at that coral reef upon becoming old enough to breed.
This deepens the mystery. If most shrimp leave their home reef by breeding age, the genetic distinguishability of shrimp between reefs is more surprising.
E
Ocean currents probably carry many of the baby shrimp hatched at a given Indonesian coral reef out into the open ocean rather than to another coral reef.
This does not state that shrimp are rarely exchanged between reefs, only that many do not end up at any reef. It does not explain why the baby shrimp that are exchanged between reefs fail to breed with each other.

24 comments

Researchers have studied the cost-effectiveness of growing halophytes—salt-tolerant plant species—for animal forage. Halophytes require more water than conventional crops, but can be irrigated with seawater, and pumping seawater into farms near sea level is much cheaper than pumping freshwater from deep wells. Thus, seawater agriculture near sea level should be cost-effective in desert regions although its yields are smaller than traditional, freshwater agriculture.

Summarize Argument
The author concludes that seawater agriculture should be cost-effective in desert regions near sea level. He supports this by saying that salt-tolerant plants (halophytes) require more water but can be irrigated with seawater, which is much cheaper to pump than freshwater.

Notable Assumptions
The author assumes that seawater agriculture is cost-effective simply because seawater irrigation is cost-effective. He assumes that the benefits of seawater irrigation outweigh any other potential costs of seawater agriculture, like higher fertilizer or equipment costs.

A
A given volume of halophytes is significantly different in nutritional value for animal forage from the same volume of conventional forage crops.
This doesn't tell us if halophytes are more or less nutritious than conventional crops for animal forage. Knowing they have "significantly different" nutritional value doesn't help to establish that halophytes are more cost-effective.
B
Some halophytes not only tolerate seawater but require salt in order to thrive.
The author says that halophytes are salt-tolerant and that they’re more cost-effective because they can be irrigated with seawater. In other words, she already assumes that the plants will be irrigated with salt water. The fact that they require salt is irrelevant.
C
Large research expenditures are needed to develop the strains of halophytes best suited for agricultural purposes.
This weakens the argument by presenting another cost of halophytes. If seawater agriculture requires expensive research, it might not actually be more cost-effective overall.
D
Costs other than the costs of irrigation are different for halophytes grown by means of seawater irrigation than for conventional crops.
The fact that other halophyte costs are “different” from conventional crop costs doesn't tell us if halophytes are more or less expensive overall.
E
Pumping water for irrigation is proportionally one of the largest costs involved in growing, harvesting, and distributing any forage crop for animals.
If irrigation is one of the largest costs in producing forage crops, this suggests that seawater agriculture may indeed be more cost-effective in certain areas, since seawater irrigation is much cheaper.

12 comments

Researcher: Every year approximately the same number of people die of iatrogenic “disease”—that is, as a direct result of medical treatments or hospitalization—as die of all other causes combined. Therefore, if medicine could find ways of preventing all iatrogenic disease, the number of deaths per year would decrease by half.

Summarize Argument
The author concludes that the number of deaths per year would decrease by half if medicine could prevent all iatrogenic disease. This is based on the fact that as many people die of iatrogenic disease (deaths from medical treatments or hospitalization) as die of all other causes combined.

Identify and Describe Flaw
The author overlooks the possibility that if people didn’t die of iatrogenic disease, they might die of other causes (such as the illnesses that required them to be hospitalized or to undergo treatment). So even if we could prevent iatrogenic disease, the number of deaths per year would not go down by half.

A
prevention of noniatrogenic disease will have an effect on the occurrence of iatrogenic disease
The argument concerns what would happen if we could get rid of iatrogenic disease. It’s not clear what impact prevention of noniatrogenic disease has on the reasoning.
B
some medical treatments can be replaced by less invasive or damaging alternatives
The author never assumed that no medical treatment could be replaced by less invasive/damaging alternatives. So pointing out that such replacements are possible doesn’t undermine the reasoning of the argument.
C
people who do not die of one cause may soon die of another cause
This possibility points out that the number of deaths per year would not necessarily decrease by half, even if iatrogenic disease were prevented. People who don’t die from hospitalization might instead die from something else.
D
there is no one way to prevent all cases of death from iatrogenic disease
The conclusion is conditioned on medicine finding ways of preventing iatrogenic disease. The conclusion doesn’t assume that this is possible. It only assumes what would result IF it were possible. So pointing out that prevention is not possible doesn’t undermine the argument.
E
whenever a noniatrogenic disease occurs, there is a risk of iatrogenic disease
We already know that iatrogenic disease results from treatments/hospitalization. So the author would already acknowledge that iatrogenic disease might result from other kinds of diseases. The conclusion doesn’t assume that eliminating iatrogenic disease is actually possible.

21 comments