Not all works of art represent something, but some do, and their doing so is relevant to our aesthetic experience of them; representation is therefore an aesthetically relevant property. Whether a work of art possesses this property is dependent upon context. Yet there are no clear criteria for determining whether context-dependent properties are present in an object, so there cannot be any clear criteria for determining whether an object qualifies as art.

Summarize Argument
Our argument concludes that there are no guidelines for defining objects as art. It supports that conclusion by identifying an attribute called representation, which is present in some art and dependent upon the art’s context. The argument then says there are no guidelines for determining aspects of art that rely on context (including representation), which the argument then stretches into the conclusion that there are no guidelines for defining art.

Identify and Describe Flaw
What if determining whether or not an object has representation is not the only way to identify it as art? Our author never defined representation as a necessary aspect for art; in fact, they told us that only some art has it. They failed to exclude the possibility that other attributes are sufficient for calling something art.

A
because some works of art are nonrepresentational, there is no way of judging our aesthetic experience of them
Our conclusion depends on characteristics and relationships associated with representational art; because this AC deals with nonrepresentational art, it goes outside the scope of our argument and does not correctly identify a flaw.
B
an object may have some aesthetic properties and not be a work of art
Irrelevant. Similarly to A, this AC goes outside the scope of our argument—we’re dealing with one specific aesthetic property and things that are art, not with other properties or non-art things.
C
aesthetically relevant properties other than representation can determine whether an object is a work of art
This addresses our argument’s underlying assumption. If aesthetically relevant properties other than representation can qualify something as art, our author’s argument is moot.
D
some works of art may have properties that are not relevant to our aesthetic experience of them
This is consistent with the argument and does not impact the validity of its conclusion. Properties like weight or smell probably don’t impact an artwork's aesthetic. The truth of this statement has nothing to do with our conclusion and does not make its logic flawed.
E
some objects that represent things other than themselves are not works of art
Similarly to A and B, this AC reaches outside the scope of our argument. The stimulus focuses on things that are art and have context-dependent properties. If something is not art, that does not impact the strength of the conclusion.

97 comments

Whenever she considers voting in an election to select one candidate for a position and there is at least one issue important to her, Kay uses the following principle in choosing which course of action to take: it is acceptable for me to vote for a candidate whose opinions differ from mine on at least one issue important to me whenever I disagree with each of the other candidates on even more such issues; it is otherwise unacceptable to vote for that candidate. In the upcoming mayoral election, the three candidates are Legrand, Medina, and Norton. There is only one issue important to Kay, and only Medina shares her opinion on that issue.

Summary
When there’s at least one issue important to Kay, then it’s acceptable for her to vote for a person with whom she disagrees on an important issue IF she disagrees with every other candidate on a greater number of important issues. If she does not disagree with every other candidate on a greater number of important issues, she cannot vote for a person with whom she disagrees about an important issue. In the upcoming election, the three candidates are L, M, and N. There’s only 1 issue important to Kay. Kay agrees with M on that issue, but she disagrees with N and L on that issue.

Notable Valid Inferences
The question stem asks us to draw an inference about "any" election. So we should pick an answer that logically follows from one of the principles. The details about the upcoming mayoral election aren't relevant to this question stem.

A
If there are no issues important to her, it is unacceptable for her to vote for any candidate in the election.
Could be false. We don’t know what is acceptable or unacceptable when there are no issues important to Kay.
B
If she agrees with each of the candidates on most of the issues important to her, it is unacceptable for her to vote for any candidate in the election.
Could be false. It’s acceptable for her to vote for one of the candidates if she disagrees with all the other candidates on a greater number of important issues. Maybe she agrees with one cand. on 80% of imp. issues, but with the other candidates only on 70%.
C
If she agrees with a particular candidate on only one issue important to her, it is unacceptable for her to vote for that candidate.
Could be false. It’s acceptable for her to vote for that candidate if she disagrees with each of the other candidates on a greater number of important issues. She might disagree with the other candidates on every issue, for example.
D
If she disagrees with each of the candidates on exactly three issues important to her, it is unacceptable for her to vote for any candidate in the election.
Must be true. If she doesn’t disagree with each of the other candidates on a greater number of important issues, it’s unacceptable for her to vote for a candidate with whom she disagrees on an important issue. Here, she disagrees with each candidate on the same # of imp. issues.
E
If there are more issues important to her on which she disagrees with a particular candidate than there are such issues on which she agrees with that candidate, it is unacceptable for her to vote for that candidate.
Could be false. It’s acceptable for her to vote for that candidate if she disagrees with each other candidate on a greater number of important issues. She might disagree with one candidate on 55% of imp. issues, but disagree with everyone else on 70%, for example.

52 comments

The widespread staff reductions in a certain region’s economy are said to be causing people who still have their jobs to cut back on new purchases as though they, too, had become economically distressed. Clearly, however, actual spending by such people is undiminished, because there has been no unusual increase in the amount of money held by those people in savings accounts.

Summarize Argument: Counter-Position
The author looks at a trend of job losses and concludes that, contrary to what some people say, those who have managed to keep their jobs are spending just as much money as they ever have, rather than reining in spending. As evidence, the author points out that these employed people haven’t been increasing the size of their savings accounts.

Describe Method of Reasoning
The author counters a position held by others. She does this by first predicting a cause-and-effect relationship that we’d expect to see if that other position were true: if employed people really were reducing their spending, their savings accounts would likely grow as a result. The author then shows that the effect (more savings) hasn’t occurred, which undermines the likelihood that the cause (reduced spending) has occurred either.

A
concluding that since an expected consequence of a supposed development did not occur, that development itself did not take place
The supposed development is a reduction in spending by people who are still employed, and the expected consequence is unusual growth in those people’s saving accounts. The author concludes that since there’s been no unusual growth, there’s been no reduction in spending.
B
concluding that since only one of the two predictable consequences of a certain kind of behavior is observed to occur, this observed occurrence cannot, in the current situation, be a consequence of such behavior
The author only identifies one predictable consequence of reducing spending—namely, a growth in savings accounts. Also, the conclusion isn’t about whether something is the consequence of a certain behavior—rather, the conclusion is that the behavior itself isn’t occurring.
C
arguing that since people’s economic behavior is guided by economic self-interest, only misinformation or error will cause people to engage in economic behavior that harms them economically
The author never raises the subjects of economic self-interest, misinformation, error, or economically harmful behavior.
D
arguing that since two alternative developments exhaust all the plausible possibilities, one of those developments occurred and the other did not
This ignores reasoning by cause-and-effect, which is central to the author’s argument. Instead, (D) describes the following, very different argument: since employed people either did or did not reduce spending, it must be that they did not reduce spending.
E
concluding that since the evidence concerning a supposed change is ambiguous, it is most likely that no change is actually taking place
The only evidence presented is clear, not ambiguous. The author states, without any ambiguity, that there’s been no unusual increase in the size of employed people’s savings accounts.

34 comments

Which one of the following inferences is most supported by the passage?

This is a Most Strongly Supported question.

Vitamin XYZ has long been a favorite among health food enthusiasts.

Forget about vitamins with only 1 letter. Vitamin B? Vitamin D? Get out of here. You need vitamin XYZ.

In a recent large study, those who took large amounts of vitamin XYZ daily for two years showed on average a 40 percent lower risk of heart disease than did members of a control group.

This sentence gives us something very common on the LSAT, and something very uncommon. What’s common is that we get a correlation between taking vitamin XYZ daily and having a significantly lower risk of heart disease. What’s uncommon is that the stimulus gives us something closer to the ideal experiment than we typically see. This is a large study, with a control group, showing a large effect size (40 percent). All three are features that will help to establish a causal explanation of the results: that the reduction of heart disease risk is because of vitamin XYZ.

At this point, I only see one potential failing of this experiment: we don’t yet know whether the people in the control group are similar to the people in the vitamin XYZ group in features that could affect rates of heart disease. In other words, was group assignment randomized? Let’s keep reading the stimulus.

Researchers corrected for differences in relevant habits, such as diet.

Unclear whether the group assignment was randomized, but these researchers do know what they’re doing. They’ve controlled for “differences in relevant habits” – that gets rid of a whole host of potential alternate causes for the correlation between vitamin XYZ and lower risk of heart disease. Exercise habits? That was controlled for. Eating fatty foods? That was controlled for. There’s still some things that aren’t controlled for, such as the genetics of the two groups. It’s possible that the control group might just, by coincidence, be more genetically vulnerable to heart disease than the vitamin XYZ group. Possible, but not very likely, and we don’t have any reason to think this might have happened.

So what can we have in mind before going to the answers? We got some pretty strong evidence of a causal relationship between vitamin XYZ and lower heart disease. The fact that there was a control group and the researchers controlled for other factors relevant to heart disease is what makes the evidence strong.

Answer Choice (A) Taking large amounts of vitamins is probably worth risking the side effects.

There are at least three issues with (A). First, the idea of “worth” is a prescriptive claim, or in other words, involves a value judgment. But we don’t know from the stimulus how to tell what’s worth anything – there’s no standard we can use to say whether vitamins are worth risking the side effects. Second, what “side effects?” The stimulus contained no information about side effects. Hence, we cannot do acost-benefit analysis. Third, the claim in this answer is about “all vitamins” but the stimulus only talked about vitamin XYZ. If we generalize from one specific vitamin to all vitamins, we will have committed the reasoning flaw of making a hasty generalization.

Correct Answer Choice (B) Those who take large doses of vitamin XYZ daily for the next two years will exhibit on average an increase in the likelihood of avoiding heart disease.

This prediction is supported by the stimulus because evidence of causation is strong. (B) matches up with what we were told about the vitamin XYZ group – it’s about taking large amounts of vitamin XYZ daily for two years. (B) also avoids over-generalizing by not saying that everyone will avoid heart disease or that most people will avoid heart disease. It says instead that the group of vitamin-takers will “on average” have an increased likelihood of avoiding heart disease. That’s moderate enough to be supported on this evidence.

Answer Choice (C) Li, who has taken large amounts of vitamin XYZ daily for the past two years, has a 40 percent lower risk of heart disease than she did two years ago.

This answer is far less supported than (B), because it’s about an individual person. Strong evidence of correlation can provide evidence of cause, but this works only on the level of group averages.

For example, we know that smoking causes lung cancer. But does that mean that every single person who smokes will develop lung cancer? No. There are many causal forces at play. Some, e.g., better genetics, may push against getting lung cancer.

So in this case, we just don’t know whether Li will have a reduced risk of heart disease. Maybe she won’t get that kind of benefit because of her genetics or her lifestyle habits?

In addition, the stimulus specifically said that the vitamin XYZ group showed “on average a 40 percent lower risk of heart disease.” That means the 40 percent figure is an average – that doesn’t mean that each individual person in the group experienced a 40 percent decrease in their risk of heart disease. If one person had a decrease of 30 percent and another person a decrease of 50 percent, that produces a 40 percent average (if those were the only 2 people in the group).

Answer Choice (D) Taking large amounts of vitamin XYZ daily over the course of one’s adult life should be recommended to most adults.

There are at least three issues with this answer.

First, we don’t want to overlook the potential negative effects of taking vitamin XYZ. Just because there’s evidence vitamin XYZ seems to reduce risk of heart disease, that doesn’t mean that people should take it. What if vitamin XYZ has side effects that make one more likely to develop Alzheimer’s disease or dementia?

Second, this answer contains the prescriptive word “should.” It’s telling people what they should do. But the stimulus doesn’t give us any standard by which we can know what people should do. Is a lower risk of heart disease something that most people should try to achieve? I think so and you’d probably agree. But that’s not a position that the stimulus supports.

Third, the experiment in the stimulus showed positive results after the participants took these vitamins for two years. We cannot infer that results will still be positive if they take them “over the course of one’s adult life.”

Answer Choice (E) Health food enthusiasts are probably correct in believing that large daily doses of multiple vitamins promote good health.

The study specifically examines the effects of vitamin XYZ on heart disease risk. (E), however, generalizes this to "multiple vitamins" and their impact on "good health" broadly. We cannot assume the effects observed from one particular vitamin to be the same for all vitamins. Likewise, good health encompasses numerous factors beyond heart disease risk, and the study does not provide evidence about the impact (positive or negative) of vitamin XYZ on these other factors.

Moreover, this answer is also wrong when it refers to health food enthusiasts probably being “correct in believing” something. The stimulus doesn’t tell us what health food enthusiasts believe. We know that they seem to like vitamin XYZ – but the stimulus doesn’t say exactly why they like vitamin XYZ, or that they like other vitamins besides XYZ.


91 comments