Today’s farmers plant only a handful of different strains of a given crop. Crops lack the diversity that they had only a few generations ago. Hence, a disease that strikes only a few strains of crops, and that would have had only minor impact on the food supply in the past, would devastate it today.

Summarize Argument
The author concludes that a disease that would have had minor impacts on food supply in the past would be devastating today. This prediction is based on the observation that today’s crops lack diversity compared to crops in the past because farmers today only plant a few strains of a given crop.

Notable Assumptions
The author assumes that farmers today don’t have any way besides diversity to protect against diseases.

A
In the past, crop diseases would often devastate food supplies throughout entire regions.
The conclusion discusses specifically the diseases that would have had only minor impacts on the food supply in the past; the diseases referenced in (A) are outside of the scope of the argument.
B
Affected crops can quickly be replaced from seed banks that store many strains of those crops.
This weakens the argument. It gives a reason that a disease that would have had a minor impact on the food supply in the past would not be devastating today: today’s farmers have another way to protect against the disease other than crop diversity.
C
Some of the less popular seed strains that were used in the past were more resistant to many diseases than are the strains popular today.
This compares the less popular strains of the past with the popular modern strains; this comparison isn’t relevant. (C) also tells us that some old strains were more robust than the popular modern strains, which is consistent with the claim that today’s crops are more vulnerable.
D
Humans today have more variety in their diets than in the past, but still rely heavily on cereal crops like rice and wheat.
The argument is about the crops that make up the food supply, not specifically human diets as a whole, so this is not relevant to the argument.
E
Today’s crops are much less vulnerable to damage from insects or encroachment by weeds than were crops of a few generations ago.
The argument is specifically about the damage caused by diseases; it could be the case that today’s crops are safer from insects and weeds, but that diseases are still able to devastate today’s food supply.

20 comments

The economy is doing badly. First, the real estate slump has been with us for some time. Second, car sales are at their lowest in years. Of course, had either one or the other phenomenon failed to occur, this would be consistent with the economy as a whole being healthy. But, their occurrence together makes it quite probable that my conclusion is correct.

Summary
The argument concludes that the economy is doing badly for two reasons: the first because the real estate market is in a slump and the second because car sales are low. If the economy were healthy, at least one of these two phenomena would not occur.

Strongly Supported Conclusions
If the economy were healthy then either car sales are not low, the real estate market is not in a slump, or both.

A
If car sales are at their lowest in years, then it is likely that the economy is doing badly.
We don’t know if low car sales alone is sufficient for a bad economy. Rather, the argument suggests that low car sales combined with a real estate slump lead to a bad economy.
B
If the economy is doing badly, then either the real estate market or the car sales market is not healthy.
We know that low car sales combined with a real estate slump are sufficient for a bad economy, but we do not know if these are the only two factors sufficient for a bad economy. A necessary condition’s occurrence does not imply the sufficient condition’s occurrence.
C
If the real estate market is healthy, then it is likely that the economy as a whole is healthy.
We don’t know what conditions are sufficient for a healthy economy. There could be other factors outside of the real estate market and car sales that lead to a bad economy.
D
If the economy is in a healthy state, then it is unlikely that the real estate and car sales markets are both in a slump.
The argument states that if car sales are not low or the real estate market is not in a slump, the economy is likely to be healthy. Therefore, if the economy were healthy it is likely that at least one of these phenomena occurred.
E
The bad condition of the economy implies that both the real estate and the car sales markets are doing badly.
We know that low car sales combined with a real estate slump are sufficient for a bad economy, but we do not know if these are the only two factors sufficient for a bad economy. A necessary condition’s occurrence does not imply the sufficient condition’s occurrence.

37 comments

Question Stem
This is a Flaw or Descriptive Weakening question. The key words in the question stem are "grounds for criticizing... reasoning."

Foundational Skills
Phenomenon-hypothesis
Contrapositive
False positive v. false negative

Stimulus
The question is hard because the correct answer (A) is stating something implied by what you might have anticipated while (B) brings up a novel though irrelevant consideration and (E) masquerades as an assumption that you might have spotted.

Someone played a practical joke on Franklin. He doesn't know who did it though he suspects Miller because Miller "has always been jealous of me." Okay, that's motive. But what evidence does he have? Just one piece: a handwritten note where the handwriting does not match Miller's.

So, what conclusion can we draw? Well, you and I are thinking, it's unclear. The fact (phenomenon) that the handwriting doesn't match Miller's could be explained by a number of hypotheses:

1. It was Miller and she disguised her handwriting.
2. It was Miller and an unwitting accomplice wrote the note.
3. It was Miller and she had a willing co-conspirator write the note.
4. It was not Miller.

Franklin jumps to hypothesis (4) as the explanation. He assumes that if the handwriting doesn't match Miller's, then Miller didn't do it. Hypotheses (1) - (3) reveal why that assumption is problematic. It could be the case that the handwriting doesn't match Miller's and (yet) it is still Miller who did it.

Now that we've identified the issue with this argument both using the framework of assumptions and alternative hypotheses, we now can think about how to "criticize Franklin's reasoning."

At a very abstract and general level, we could say something like "It (Franklin's reasoning) fails to consider alternative hypotheses." That would capture hypotheses (1) through (3). That could be a correct answer, if all the other answers are bad. But the correct answer could also be (and in fact turns out to be) more specific.

Answer Choice (A)
(A) says that Franklin's reasoning "fails to consider the possibility that there was more than one practical joker." On first blush, you might think that this is merely descriptively accurate yet doesn't get to the weakness in the reasoning. True, you think, Franklin did not consider that this could have been a conspiracy (a plot involving more than one person). But how many people involved is not the issue. The issue is the identity of those involved.

Ah, but the number of people involved is related to the identity of those involved. Why did Franklin write off Miller? Precisely because he didn't consider that Miller could have had an accomplice, that there could have been more than one practical joker.

Do you see how the test writers made (A) subtle? They could have said "It fails to consider the possibility that Miller had an accomplice." That would have been the blunt and obvious way to state the weakness in Franklin's reasoning. But they didn't. Instead they stated something implied by the blunt version of the hypothesis. If it's true that Miller had an accomplice, then it must be true that there was more than one practical joker.

Answer Choice (B)
(B) says that Franklin's reasoning "fails to indicate the degree to which handwriting samples should look alike in order to be considered of the same source." This is true. It's descriptively accurate. Franklin merely asserts "the handwriting is not hers" without providing any reason for us to believe that assertion, e.g. just how closely must the curve on an "r" match or what angles of "v" or "w" are considered close enough?

All true. But, notice that that assertion "the handwriting is not hers" is being used as a premise. And as a rule of thumb, premises get the benefit of the presumption of truth. If Franklin asserts it, then, unless we have reasons to doubt him, we accept it as true. (B) is asking us to question this premise.

If we were detectives and if this were an actual investigation or criminal trial, then, yeah, this assertion absolutely would come under attack: we'd get experts to explain their methodology and testify so we can ascertain whether to believe Franklin's assertion that "the handwriting is not hers." But, we're doing an LR question. We're just being asked to "criticize Franklin's reasoning" and the rule of thumb is that you do not attack premises. Plus, as we already saw in the stimulus analysis, even granting Franklin the truth of this premise still leaves his argument vulnerable because the issue isn't in this premise. The issue is in the support relationship between this premise and the conclusion.

Answer Choice (C)
(C) says that no explanation was provided for why Miller should be the prime suspect. This is false. It's descriptively inaccurate. Franklin does give an explanation. He says that Miller "has always been jealous" of him. Now, you might think that's a weak motive, but that doesn't change the fact that Franklin gave an explanation. You're just judging that explanation as insufficient. No explanation is different from an explanation that you don't believe.

Answer Choice (D)
(D) says that no explanation was provided for why only one piece of evidence was obtained. This is true, it's descriptively accurate. Franklin did not explain why there isn't more evidence. But so what. From the sole existing piece of evidence Franklin drew a conclusion. That reasoning is present and weak. Our job is to attack that reasoning. That's it. It's not to ask questions that would have been relevant had we been actually investigating this case. Had we been actual detectives actually trying to solve the case, then yeah, we wonder why there was just one piece of evidence.

If you chose (D), you might have been thinking that Franklin's argument is weak because there was only one piece of evidence provided. That is true. But that's not what (D) says. In order to capture your justified concern, (D) should have said something like "It draws a conclusion unsupported by the only piece of evidence available."

Answer Choice (E)
(E) says that Franklin's reasoning "takes for granted" which is just "assumes" that - and here comes the conditional - "if the handwriting on the note had been Miller's, then the identity of the joker would have been ascertained to be Miller:"

match → Miller

(E) is testing your conditional logic with a classic sufficiency-necessity confusion. It also helps if you're familiar with the distinction between false positives and false negatives.

We figured out that Franklin does "take for granted" that if the handwriting didn't match Miller's, then Miller didn't do it:

/match → /Miller

What's the contrapositive of that? If Miller did it, then the handwriting would have matched:

Miller → match

(E)'s match → Miller is just not the same as Miller → match. You don't want to confuse sufficiency for necessity because, well, they're different. In the context of using a test result to determine identity, here's why they are different.

Let's stipulate that the handwriting analysis test that Franklin used was one that contains high false positives but low false negatives.

A false positive is when the test says "match!" but it should not have. The positive result ("match!") was false. Like if a doctor pronounced a man "pregnant!" That's a false positive. Or if a DNA analysis said "match!" but it shouldn't have because there was an error. We'd be rightly suspicious of positive results from tests that contain high rates of false positive. "Sure, test, you say it matches, but you always say that. I don't believe you."

But don't confuse that for when the test gives you negative results. The test could be highly reliable for negative results even if it's unreliable for positive results.

What's a false negative? It's when a test says "no match!" but it should have matched. The negative result was false. Like if a doctor pronounced an obviously 8 month pregnant woman "Not pregnant! Just lay off the chips." That's a false negative. Or if a DNA analysis said "no match!" but it should have said "match!" instead.

Since we stipulated that our handwriting analysis test contains few false negatives, we don't have these concerns. That means whenever the test says "no match," we should believe it. Truly there is no match.

That means it's reasonable to hold the position that /match → /Miller while rejecting the position that match → Miller. The two positions are not the same. The first position requires a test with low false negatives. The second position requires a test with low false positives.


48 comments

Franklin: The only clue I have as to the identity of the practical joker is the handwriting on the note. Ordinarily I would suspect Miller, who has always been jealous of me, but the handwriting is not hers. So the joker is apparently someone else.

Summarize Argument
The author hypothesizes that the practical joker must be someone besides Miller. This is because the only clue about the identity of the practical joker is the handwriting on the note, and the handwriting isn’t Miller’s.

Identify and Describe Flaw
The author overlooks the possibility that Miller could have been the practical joker and enlisted someone else to write the note. The correct answer should relate to why Miller could have been the practical joker despite the handwriting not being hers.

A
It fails to consider the possibility that there was more than one practical joker.
If there were more than one practical joker, then Miller could have been one of them and someone else could have written the note. This possibility undermines the argument, and the author fails to consider it.
B
It fails to indicate the degree to which handwriting samples should look alike in order to be considered of the same source.
We already know that the handwriting is not Miller’s. This is a premise we accept. The exact degree of difference between Miller’s handwriting and the handwriting on the note therefore doesn’t matter.
C
It provides no explanation for why Miller should be the prime suspect.
The author’s conclusion is simply that the joker is not Miller. Why Miller was initially suspected doesn’t relate to whether or not Miller is the joker based on the handwriting sample.
D
It provides no explanation for why only one piece of evidence was obtained.
The author doesn’t need to explain why only one piece of evidence was obtained. The author is allowed to make an argument based on whatever evidence is available.
E
It takes for granted that if the handwriting on the note had been Miller’s, then the identity of the joker would have been ascertained to be Miller.
This confuses sufficient and necessary conditions. The author assumes that if the handwriting isn’t Miller’s, then Miller is not the joker. But this doesn’t imply that if the handwriting were Miller’s, it would prove Miller was the joker.

Question Stem
This is a Flaw or Descriptive Weakening question. The key words in the question stem are "grounds for criticizing... reasoning."

Foundational Skills
Phenomenon-hypothesis
Contrapositive
False positive v. false negative

Stimulus
The question is hard because the correct answer (A) is stating something implied by what you might have anticipated while (B) brings up a novel though irrelevant consideration and (E) masquerades as an assumption that you might have spotted.

Someone played a practical joke on Franklin. He doesn't know who did it though he suspects Miller because Miller "has always been jealous of me." Okay, that's motive. But what evidence does he have? Just one piece: a handwritten note where the handwriting does not match Miller's.

So, what conclusion can we draw? Well, you and I are thinking, it's unclear. The fact (phenomenon) that the handwriting doesn't match Miller's could be explained by a number of hypotheses:

1. It was Miller and she disguised her handwriting.
2. It was Miller and an unwitting accomplice wrote the note.
3. It was Miller and she had a willing co-conspirator write the note.
4. It was not Miller.

Franklin jumps to hypothesis (4) as the explanation. He assumes that if the handwriting doesn't match Miller's, then Miller didn't do it. Hypotheses (1) - (3) reveal why that assumption is problematic. It could be the case that the handwriting doesn't match Miller's and (yet) it is still Miller who did it.

Now that we've identified the issue with this argument both using the framework of assumptions and alternative hypotheses, we now can think about how to "criticize Franklin's reasoning."

At a very abstract and general level, we could say something like "It (Franklin's reasoning) fails to consider alternative hypotheses." That would capture hypotheses (1) through (3). That could be a correct answer, if all the other answers are bad. But the correct answer could also be (and in fact turns out to be) more specific.

Answer Choice (A)
(A) says that Franklin's reasoning "fails to consider the possibility that there was more than one practical joker." On first blush, you might think that this is merely descriptively accurate yet doesn't get to the weakness in the reasoning. True, you think, Franklin did not consider that this could have been a conspiracy (a plot involving more than one person). But how many people involved is not the issue. The issue is the identity of those involved.

Ah, but the number of people involved is related to the identity of those involved. Why did Franklin write off Miller? Precisely because he didn't consider that Miller could have had an accomplice, that there could have been more than one practical joker.

Do you see how the test writers made (A) subtle? They could have said "It fails to consider the possibility that Miller had an accomplice." That would have been the blunt and obvious way to state the weakness in Franklin's reasoning. But they didn't. Instead they stated something implied by the blunt version of the hypothesis. If it's true that Miller had an accomplice, then it must be true that there was more than one practical joker.

Answer Choice (B)
(B) says that Franklin's reasoning "fails to indicate the degree to which handwriting samples should look alike in order to be considered of the same source." This is true. It's descriptively accurate. Franklin merely asserts "the handwriting is not hers" without providing any reason for us to believe that assertion, e.g. just how closely must the curve on an "r" match or what angles of "v" or "w" are considered close enough?

All true. But, notice that that assertion "the handwriting is not hers" is being used as a premise. And as a rule of thumb, premises get the benefit of the presumption of truth. If Franklin asserts it, then, unless we have reasons to doubt him, we accept it as true. (B) is asking us to question this premise.

If we were detectives and if this were an actual investigation or criminal trial, then, yeah, this assertion absolutely would come under attack: we'd get experts to explain their methodology and testify so we can ascertain whether to believe Franklin's assertion that "the handwriting is not hers." But, we're doing an LR question. We're just being asked to "criticize Franklin's reasoning" and the rule of thumb is that you do not attack premises. Plus, as we already saw in the stimulus analysis, even granting Franklin the truth of this premise still leaves his argument vulnerable because the issue isn't in this premise. The issue is in the support relationship between this premise and the conclusion.

Answer Choice (C)
(C) says that no explanation was provided for why Miller should be the prime suspect. This is false. It's descriptively inaccurate. Franklin does give an explanation. He says that Miller "has always been jealous" of him. Now, you might think that's a weak motive, but that doesn't change the fact that Franklin gave an explanation. You're just judging that explanation as insufficient. No explanation is different from an explanation that you don't believe.

Answer Choice (D)
(D) says that no explanation was provided for why only one piece of evidence was obtained. This is true, it's descriptively accurate. Franklin did not explain why there isn't more evidence. But so what. From the sole existing piece of evidence Franklin drew a conclusion. That reasoning is present and weak. Our job is to attack that reasoning. That's it. It's not to ask questions that would have been relevant had we been actually investigating this case. Had we been actual detectives actually trying to solve the case, then yeah, we wonder why there was just one piece of evidence.

If you chose (D), you might have been thinking that Franklin's argument is weak because there was only one piece of evidence provided. That is true. But that's not what (D) says. In order to capture your justified concern, (D) should have said something like "It draws a conclusion unsupported by the only piece of evidence available."

Answer Choice (E)
(E) says that Franklin's reasoning "takes for granted" which is just "assumes" that - and here comes the conditional - "if the handwriting on the note had been Miller's, then the identity of the joker would have been ascertained to be Miller:"

match → Miller

(E) is testing your conditional logic with a classic sufficiency-necessity confusion. It also helps if you're familiar with the distinction between false positives and false negatives.

We figured out that Franklin does "take for granted" that if the handwriting didn't match Miller's, then Miller didn't do it:

/match → /Miller

What's the contrapositive of that? If Miller did it, then the handwriting would have matched:

Miller → match

(E)'s match → Miller is just not the same as Miller → match. You don't want to confuse sufficiency for necessity because, well, they're different. In the context of using a test result to determine identity, here's why they are different.

Let's stipulate that the handwriting analysis test that Franklin used was one that contains high false positives but low false negatives.

A false positive is when the test says "match!" but it should not have. The positive result ("match!") was false. Like if a doctor pronounced a man "pregnant!" That's a false positive. Or if a DNA analysis said "match!" but it shouldn't have because there was an error. We'd be rightly suspicious of positive results from tests that contain high rates of false positive. "Sure, test, you say it matches, but you always say that. I don't believe you."

But don't confuse that for when the test gives you negative results. The test could be highly reliable for negative results even if it's unreliable for positive results.

What's a false negative? It's when a test says "no match!" but it should have matched. The negative result was false. Like if a doctor pronounced an obviously 8 month pregnant woman "Not pregnant! Just lay off the chips." That's a false negative. Or if a DNA analysis said "no match!" but it should have said "match!" instead.

Since we stipulated that our handwriting analysis test contains few false negatives, we don't have these concerns. That means whenever the test says "no match," we should believe it. Truly there is no match.

That means it's reasonable to hold the position that /match → /Miller while rejecting the position that match → Miller. The two positions are not the same. The first position requires a test with low false negatives. The second position requires a test with low false positives.


56 comments

The people most likely to watch a televised debate between political candidates are the most committed members of the electorate and thus the most likely to have already made up their minds about whom to support. Furthermore, following a debate, uncommitted viewers are generally undecided about who won the debate. Hence, winning a televised debate does little to bolster one’s chances of winning an election.

A
watching an exciting debate makes people more likely to vote in an election
We don't know if the debate is exciting. Also, the people most likely to watch it are already committed voters. But even if it is exciting and causes more people to vote, (A) doesn't address the conclusion that winning it doesn't improve one’s chances of winning the election.
B
the voting behavior of people who do not watch a televised debate is influenced by reports about the debate
The author only addresses how televised debates affect viewers, saying that many are already committed to one candidate and the rest are unsure who won. But he fails to address how televised debates affect non-viewers. Their votes might be influenced by reports about the debate.
C
there are differences of opinion about what constitutes winning or losing a debate
The premises state that many viewers are already committed to one candidate or another; it makes sense that they’d be likely to disagree about who won the debate. But this doesn’t affect the conclusion that winning doesn’t impact one’s chance of winning the election.
D
people’s voting behavior may be influenced in unpredictable ways by comments made by the participants in a televised debate
Whether voting behavior is influenced in “unpredictable ways” by a debate doesn’t affect the conclusion that winning a debate doesn’t impact one’s chances of winning the election. Are these “unpredictable ways” positive or negative for the winner? We just don’t know.
E
people who are committed to a particular candidate will vote even if their candidate is perceived as having lost a televised debate
The author doesn’t fail to consider this. He explicitly says that, because many viewers are committed to a particular candidate, winning or not winning a debate doesn’t affect one’s chance of winning an election.

26 comments