Game show host: Humans are no better than apes at investing, that is, they do not attain a better return on their investments than apes do. We gave five stock analysts and one chimpanzee $1,350 each to invest. After one month, the chimp won, having increased its net worth by $210. The net worth of the analyst who came in second increased by only $140.

Summarize Argument
The game show host concludes that humans are no better than apes at investing. She supports this with an experiment in which five stock analysts and one chimpanzee were each given $1,350 to invest. After one month, the chimpanzee increased its net worth by $210, while the top analyst increased by only $140.

Identify and Describe Flaw
There are many flaws with the game show host’s argument and experiment. First is the cookie-cutter flaw of hasty generalization. She makes a generalization about all people based on a study of five, and about all apes based on a study of one chimpanzee. She also draws a conclusion about investing in general based on one small experiment that involved only short-term investing; she never considers the analysts’ and chimpanzee’s potential long-term results.

A
A conclusion is drawn about apes in general on the basis of an experiment involving one chimpanzee.
This is the cookie-cutter flaw of hasty generalization. The host broadly concludes that humans are no better than apes at investing based on an experiment involving only one chimpanzee. Would other chimpanzees have had similar success? What about other kinds of apes?
B
No evidence is offered that chimpanzees are capable of understanding stock reports and making reasoned investment decisions.
This is true, but it isn’t a flaw. The host concludes that humans are no better at investing than apes, based on an experiment where an ape made more money investing than humans did. It doesn’t matter if the ape understood investing, just that it performed better than the humans.
C
A broad conclusion is drawn about the investment skills of humans on the basis of what is known about five humans.
This is the cookie-cutter flaw of hasty generalization. The host broadly concludes that humans in general are no better than apes at investing based on an experiment involving only five humans.
D
Too general a conclusion is made about investing on the basis of a single experiment involving short-term investing but not long-term investing.
This is yet another example of the host’s overgeneralization. She draws a general conclusion about all investing based on one experiment that only involved short-term investing.
E
No evidence is considered about the long-term performance of the chimpanzee’s portfolio versus that of the analysts’ portfolios.
This is another one of the host’s flaws. She draws a conclusion about investing based on a very short (one month) experiment. She overlooks the fact that the results could be different after multiple months or years, especially since investing is often a long-term process.

37 comments

Human beings have cognitive faculties that are superior to those of other animals, and once humans become aware of these, they cannot be made happy by anything that does not involve gratification of these faculties.

The stimulus does not provide an argument, just a pair of claims. First, humans have superior cognitive abilities compared to other animals. Second, once humans are aware of their superior cognitive faculties, they can only achieve happiness through activities that involve gratifying their cognitive faculties.

Notable Assumptions
The stimulus assumes that both of the claims presented are factually true. This means it assumes:
that no animals have superior cognitive faculties compared to humans; and also
that no humans who are aware of their superior cognition can be made happy through non-cognitively-gratifying activities.

A
Certain animals—dolphins and chimpanzees, for example—appear to be capable of rational communication.
This does not weaken the claims in the stimulus. First, we don’t actually know if these animals actually are capable of rational communication—they just seem to be. Second, even if they were capable, we still wouldn’t know if they had superior cognition to humans.
B
Many people familiar both with intellectual stimulation and with physical pleasures enjoy the latter more.
This weakens the claims in the stimulus. People familiar with intellectual stimulation can reasonably be said to be aware of their cognitive faculties. If many such people prefer physical (i.e. non-cognitive) pleasures, that undermines the stimulus’ second claim.
C
Someone who never experienced classical music as a child will usually prefer popular music as an adult.
This does not weaken the claims in the stimulus. First, we can’t assume that classical and pop music are relevant to distinguishing cognitive and non-cognitive sources of happiness. Second, we don’t know if this “someone” is aware of their cognition, and thus within the domain.
D
Many people who are serious athletes consider themselves to be happy.
This does not weaken the claims in the stimulus. Like (E), we have no idea if this provides an example of people who are aware of their cognition but still gain happiness from non-cognitive activities—we can’t assume either of those factors.
E
Many people who are serious athletes love gourmet food.
This does not weaken the claims in the stimulus. Like (D), both factors of the stimulus’ second claim are unclear. Are serious athletes aware of their cognition or not? Is gourmet food a non-cognitive source of happiness or not? We don’t know.

66 comments

If the statements above are true, which one of the following can be most reasonably inferred from them?

This is a Most Strongly Supported question, because we are looking for what can be “most reasonably inferred” from the stimulus.

One of the great difficulties in establishing animal rights based merely on the fact that animals are living things concerns scope.

Apparently, “scope” is one of the difficulties of trying to establish animal rights based solely on the fact that animals are living things. In other words, if you argue that, because animals are living things, they deserve rights – you’ll run into a problem of “scope.”

If one construes the term “living things” broadly, one is bound to bestow rights on organisms that are not animals (e.g., plants).

This is the beginning of the stimulus’s explanation of the problem of “scope.” If we interpret “living things” broadly, we’ll have to give rights to organisms that aren’t animals. Plants are living things, aren’t they? So they’d deserve rights. But that would be too broad. It would be over-inclusive (if all we wanted to protect were animals).

But if this term is construed narrowly, one is apt to refuse rights to organisms that, at least biologically, are considered members of the animal kingdom.

What if we interpret “living things” narrowly? Then the problem of “scope” is that some things that are biologically considered animals would end up not getting rights. For example, if you interpret “living things” as only multi-celled organisms that can move from one place to another by their own power, you’d be leaving out sea sponges and barnacles from your definition, since they can’t move by themselves. But they’re biologically considered animals. So that’s the opposite problem: under-inclusive.

The last two sentences, together, describe the problem of “scope.” If you interpret “living things” broadly, some things that shouldn’t get rights will get rights: over-inclusive. But if you interpret “living things” narrowly, some things that are animals won’t end up getting rights: under-inclusive.

There’s no clear conclusion to anticipate based on the stimulus, so let’s get into the answers and identify the one that is most strongly supported via process of elimination. The correct answer is likely to have something to do with the problem of “scope,” but beyond that, it’s difficult to make any prediction.

Answer Choice (A) Not all animals should be given rights.

The stimulus does not support any normative claim about animal rights. The stimulus provides commentary on one of the difficulties that you’ll encounter if you try to justify animal rights based on the fact that animals are living things. But commentary on the problems of a particular argument in support of animal rights does not support a normative claim about who should or should not have rights. For example, if I say that one problem with trying to lose weight solely by dieting is that it relies only on willpower, I’m not expressing any opinion about whether you should or should not try to lose weight. I’m simply commenting on the effectiveness of one method of losing weight.

Answer Choice (B) One cannot bestow rights on animals without also bestowing rights on at least some plants.

(B) would be supported if two things were true: (1) We had to establish animal rights based merely on the fact that they are living things; and (2) We had to interpret “living things” broadly. If both were true, then we’d bestow rights on organisms that are not animals, such as plants. But neither has to be true. We could try to anchor animal rights to whether they are sentient or can suffer. We also don’t have to interpret “living things” broadly. We could interpret the phrase narrowly. So this answer is not correct.

Answer Choice (C) The problem of delineating the boundary of the set of living things interferes with every attempt to establish animal rights.

The correct version of (C) would go like this: The problem of delineating the boundary of the set of living things interferes with one attempt to establish animal rights.

But the original version of (C) is tempting, because the stimulus presented a problem of “scope” in connection with establishing animal rights. And, it’s fair to describe the problem of “scope” in the stimulus as the problem of delineating the boundary of the set of living things.

The flaw with this answer is that the problem of “scope” as described by the stimulus arises when you try to establish animal rights based merely on the fact that animals are living things. But that’s just one potential premise on which you might try to establish rights. And we don’t have to use that premise.

We could instead try to establish animal rights based on something else: Animals feel pain, and therefore they deserve rights. Animals are cute, and therefore they deserve rights. Animals were created by an omnipotent deity, and therefore they deserve rights. These are all different potential arguments we could make in support of animal rights. And none of these arguments relate to the boundary of “living things.” These arguments would have their own problems of scope, of course, because it’s exceedingly difficult to draw the boundaries just right. What is the set of things that feel pain? Or things that are cute? Or things that are created by an omnipotent deity? Could these sets be too broad or too narrow? Almost certainly. But the key is that these problems of scope are not related to what counts as a “living thing.”

The problem of the scope of “living things” arises only when we try to justify animal rights based solely on animals being “living things.” But it does not arise with every attempt to establish animal rights.

Correct Answer Choice (D) Successful attempts to establish rights for all animals are likely either to establish rights for some plants or not to depend solely on the observation that animals are living things.

It’s probably easier to get to (D) through process of elimination than through a complete, perfect understanding of the answer. But let’s unpack it and see why it is supported.

If we want to have a successful attempt to establish rights for all animals, what kind of interpretation of “living things” might we have? If our interpretation is narrow, the stimulus says that some things that are biologically animals won’t end up getting rights. So that’s out of the question. To establish rights for all animals, then, we can’t have a narrow interpretation.

But the only alternative interpretation of “living things” the stimulus discusses is a broad interpretation. And if we interpret “living things” broadly, then some things that aren’t animals will get rights (such as plants). So if we try to establish rights for all animals based merely on the fact that animals are living things, then we would interpret “living things” broadly, and grant rights to some plants.

But, there’s one alternative to this path. What if we try to establish rights for all animals based on some other ground besides animals being living things? In this case, we wouldn’t be forced to grant rights to plants.

So to recap, there are three potential paths to establishing animal rights:

(1) solely on the ground that animals are living things, and interpreting “living things” narrowly – this will leave some animals unprotected

(2) solely on the ground that animals are living things, and interpreting “living things” broadly – this will grant rights to plants

(3) not solely on the ground that animals are living things – there would be some other reason for animal rights besides animals being living things

Option (1) doesn’t protect all animals. So if we want to establish rights for all animals, we must go through path (2) or (3). This is what (D) says. Successful attempts to establish rights for all animals are likely to establish rights for some plants – path (2) – or not depend solely on the observation that animals are living things – path (3).

(Note that in theory, it’s possible to interpret “living things” neither too narrowly nor too broadly. So in theory, there is still a way to establish rights for all animals based on the fact they are living things, without having to grant rights to plants. This is why (D) uses the word “likely” – it doesn’t have to be certain that granting all animals rights requires path (2) or path (3); it just has to be likely. And indeed, it is likely because it’s exceedingly difficult to draw the boundaries just right.)

Answer Choice (E) The fact that animals are living things is irrelevant to the question of whether animals should or should not be accorded rights, because plants are living things too.

The stimulus describes a problem with establishing animal rights based merely on the fact that animals are living things. But this doesn’t mean the author of the stimulus believes that the fact animals are living is irrelevant to the question of their rights. It’s entirely possible that the author thinks that we should adopt a broad interpretation of “living things” and that we should be OK with granting rights to plants and other non-animals. Or, it’s possible the author thinks that the fact animals are living things is an important factor in whether they deserve rights, but should not be the only factor.

Put another way, although the author of the stimulus describes a strategic problem with establishing rights based on animals being “living things,” the stimulus does not tell us the author’s personal opinion about the importance or relevance of “living things” in establishing rights. For example, if I say that one problem with trying to lose weight solely by dieting is that it relies only on willpower, I’m not saying anything about whether dieting should play a small or large role in trying to lose weight. I’m simply describing a strategic problem with relying solely on dieting; I’m not sharing a value judgment about the importance or relevance of dieting. I might think dieting is still very important and that you should do it if you want to lose weight, despite the problem I described.


91 comments

Party spokesperson: The opposition party’s proposal to stimulate economic activity in the province by refunding $600 million in provincial taxes to taxpayers, who could be expected to spend the money, envisions an illusory benefit. Since the province’s budget is required to be in balance, either new taxes would be needed to make up the shortfall, in which case the purpose of the refund would be defeated, or else workers for the province would be dismissed. So either the province’s taxpayers or its workers, who are also residents of the province, will have the $600 million to spend, but there can be no resulting net increase in spending to stimulate the province’s economy.

Summarize Argument
The author’s main conclusion is that the proposal to stimulate economic activity in the province by refunding $600 million won’t actually benefit the province’s taxpayers. This is because the province’s budget is required to be in balance, which the author believes implies that the province will need to issue new taxes or fire workers in order to make up for the $600 million that would be going back to taxpayers.

Notable Assumptions
The author assumes that in order to balance the budget, the province must issue new taxes or fire workers.

A
taxpayers of the province would spend outside the province at least $300 million of any $600 million refunded to them
If taxpayers spend the refund out of province, that’s less money that would be spent on economic activity in the province. This supports the author’s point that the proposal won’t result in a net increase in spending in the province.
B
taxpayers of the province would receive any refund in partial payments during the year rather than in a lump sum
Whether the refund is in one lump sum or multiple payments doesn’t change the overall amount of the refund or whether the need to balance the budget necessitates new taxes or firing workers.
C
province could assess new taxes in a way that would avoid angering taxpayers
The taxpayers’ emotions have no clear impact on this argument. The author’s reasoning relates to the need to balance the budget and recoup the $600 million being refunded.
D
province could, instead of refunding the money, stimulate its economy by redirecting its spending to use the $600 million for construction projects creating jobs around the province
This answer describes a solution that doesn’t involve refunding $600 million to taxpayers. But the conclusion is about the refund and whether it will achieve its goal. Pointing out that we can do something besides a refund doesn’t undermine the author’s point.
E
province could keep its workers and use them more effectively, with a resulting savings of $600 million in its out-of-province expenditures
This points out how the need to balance the budget doesn’t require new taxes or firing workers. If we could keep workers and recoup $600 million by saving on out-of-province expenditures, then we don’t need to tax the province’s taxpayers or fire workers.

142 comments